José Enrique Rodó: The Aristocratic Element in Democracy

 

Introduction and Commentary

 

                    José Enrique Rodó (1871-1917) was an Uruguayan philosopher and politician; unlike the authors I typically translate here, he was not Catholic.  Instead, he proudly declared himself a “freethinker,” though that in no way made him abhor religion: “Believe that nothing inspires more respect in me than religious sincerity, wherever it manifests itself, whatever be the dogmas to which it lives united…Free-thinking, as I conceive and profess it, is, in its most ultimate essence, tolerance; and fruitful tolerance has to be, not merely passive, but active as well; it has to be, not merely an apathetic attitude, disdainful consent, frigid leniency, but rather an exchange of stimuli and teachings, a relation of love, a power of sympathy that penetrates into the abysses of another’s conscience, of which an indifferent heart will never be capable.  And, more than any others, religious questions are those which require this high kind of tolerance, because they are the [questions] in which, in the greatest way, one enters into the unconscious and ineffable foundation of every spirit” (“The Religious Sentiment and the Critic,” in Obras completas, 289, 290-291). 

                    He had no qualms about drawing from religions if he found truth therein.  Thus, in the passage translated below, he strives to unite the idea of the equality of each person—drawn from Christianity—with the idea of “natural aristocracy.”  The basis of this idea is the simple recognition that different people have different skills, and that some have greater skill or aptitude, in a certain field, than others do.  Some are physically stronger than others; some are better jumpers; some are better at mathematics; some are better at persuading others via charisma, etc.  Going further, concepts of “natural aristocracy” try to build a society that takes these different skills into account, a society that, necessarily, becomes hierarchical, since those better skilled in any one field become leaders of the less-skilled.  (Proponents of “natural aristocracy” typically go further and say that even the political sphere should become a hierarchy based on general skillfulness: the truly best (aristoi) should rule.)  Yet it is easy for such a hierarchy to become a denigration and oppression of those with lesser skills, a caste system with a swath of “Untouchables.”  That is why Rodó tries to counteract this tendency by drawing on the Christian idea of equality and the universal dignity of every person, and even go so far as to declare—inspired by the image of the Cross—that “hierarchical superiority in an order ought to be nothing else but a superior capacity for love.”  It is this focus on love and on how hierarchy leads to the uplifting of all, that separates his view of “natural aristocracy” from a brutal, Darwinist dictatorship of the powerful.

                    Rodó the freethinker was not the only one to have such ideas; the ornery Colombian Catholic aphoristic philosopher Nicolás Gómez-Dávila (1913-1994) emphasized similar thoughts in his own pithy way.  Thus, he argues, hierarchy is not antithetical to freethinking, but necessary: “He who repudiates dogmatism has to choose between indifferentism and hierarchy” (Escolios a un texto implícito, 319).  Likewise, instead of suppressing the weak and unskilled, it supports them: “The hierarchical order is the only one that neither expels nor suppresses…In societies where everyone believes themselves equal, the inevitable superiority of some few makes the rest feel like failures.  Inversely, in societies where inequality is the norm, each one installs himself in his own difference, without feeling the urgency, nor conceiving the possibility, of comparing himself.  Only a hierarchical structure is compassionate towards the mediocre and the humble” (Escolios, 94, 424).  The very principle of hierarchy—as opposed to a pure dictatorship of the powerful—protects those on below.  It is also, he adds, blindly obvious: “Even among fanatical egalitarians, the briefest encounter re-establishes human inequalities…There exists no individual who, measuring himself unpreparedly, does not discover himself inferior to many, superior to few, equal to none” (Escolios, 204, 478).  This hierarchical principle, Gómez-Dávila argues, is basic to all of life, even in the understanding of Catholicism itself, for “Catholicism is the hierarchical structuring of the history of religions”—that is, it takes the elements and truths buried in all other religions (“it integrates magical rite as well as mystical contemplation, ethical behavior as well as theological reasoning”) and hierarchically structures them into the full, absolute truth (Escolios, 496). 

                    It is because of the development of this idea—the integration of hierarchy and universal human dignity—in writers like Gómez-Dávila that I decided to translate the following passage from a “freethinker” like Rodó.  This passage comes from Chapter IV of Rodó’s famous essay Ariel, a rallying cry for Latin-American modernism, which argues for embracing the truths of (continental) American democracy, without being subsumed by nordomanía, “Yankee mania,” the uncritical embrace of all the over-the-top, materialistic trends in U.S. society.  Oddly, the essay is written as an address to (continental) American youth by Ariel, the spirit from Shakespeare’s The Tempest; Rodó makes Caliban, from the same play, into a principle of evil, and he also wrote a separate essay collection entitled Prospero’s Viewpoint—evidently, the play struck a cord with him.

 

 

The Aristocratic Element in Democracy

José Enrique Rodó

(from Ariel, Ch. IV; Obras completas 223-226)

 

                    No distinction is more easily confused and negated in the spirit of the people than that which teaches that democratic equality can signify an ideal possibility, but never an ideal reality, of influence and prestige among the members of an organized society.  In all of them, there is an identical right to aspire to the moral superiorities which ought to be the reason for and foundation of effective superiorities, but only to those who have really taken possession of the former ought the prize of the latter to be conceded.  The truthful, the worthy concept of equality rests upon the thought that all rational beings are endowed, by nature, with faculties capable of a noble development.  The duty of the State consists in arranging all the members of the society in the indistinct conditions which tend towards their perfecting.  The duty of the State consists in predisposing the proper means for uniformly provoking the revelation of human superiorities, wherever they exist.  In a like manner, but far from this initial equality, every inequality will be justified, because it will be the sanction of the mysterious elections of Nature or of the meritorious force of the will.—When conceived in this way, democratic equality, far from opposing the selection of customs and of ideas, is the most efficacious instrument for spiritual selection, is the providential atmosphere of culture.  All that favors the predominance of intelligent energy will favor it.  In just the same way, I can agree with de Tocqueville that poetry, eloquence, graces of the spirit, splendors of the imagination, profundity of thought, “all those gifts of the soul, scattered haphazardly by heaven,” were collaborators in the work of democracy and served it, even when they were found on the side of its adversaries, because they all converged in putting into relief the natural, the non-inherited greatness, of which our spirit is capable.—Emulation, which is the most powerful stimulus among those which can overexcite vivacity of thought as well as the other human activities, needs, at times, equality as a starting-point, in order to be produced, and inequality, which gives the advantage to the most apt and the best, as final object.  Only a democratic regime can reconcile, in its bosom, those two conditions of emulation, when it does not degenerate into a flattening egalitarianism and limit itself to considering a future equivalence of men through their ascension to the same grade of culture as a beautiful idea of perfectibility.

                    Rationally conceived, democracy always admits an imprescriptible aristocratic element, which consists in establishing the superiority of the best, assuring it with the free consent of those associated.  Like aristocracies, it consecrates the distinction of quality, but it resolves it in favor of truly superior qualities—those of virtue, character, spirit—and, without pretending to immobilize them in classes constituted apart from others, which maintain, in their own favor, the execrable privilege of caste, it ceaselessly renews its ruling aristocracy in the living fonts of the people, and it makes them accept it through justice and love.  In a like manner, recognizing, in the selection and predominance of the greatest endowments, a necessity of all progress, it excludes from that universal law of life—in order to sanction it in the order of society—the effect of humiliation and suffering that lies in the concurrences of nature and in those of the other social organizations, the hard lot of the conquered.  “The great law of natural selection”—Fouillée[1] has luminously said—“will continue to be realized in the bosom of human societies only when it is realized more and more by way of liberty.”—The odious character of traditional aristocracies originated from their being unjust in their foundation and oppressive, inasmuch as their authority was an imposition.  Today we know that there exists no other legitimate limit for human equality than that which consists in the dominion of intelligence and virtue, consented to by the liberty of all.  But we also know that it is necessary that this limit exist in reality.—On the other hand, our Christian conception of life teaches us that moral superiorities, which are a motive for rights, are principally a motive for duties, and that every superior spirit has duties towards the rest in equal proportion to how it exceeds them in the capacity for realizing the good.  Nietzsche’s anti-egalitarianism—which causes so deep a furrow in what we might call our modern literature of ideas—brought to its powerful revindication of the rights that he considers implicit in human superiorities an abominable, a reactionary spirit: seeing that, negating all brotherhood, all piety, it places in the heart of the superman whom it deifies a satanic belittling of the disinherited and the weak; and, with logical resolution, it, in the end, comes to affirm that “society does not exist for itself, but rather for its elect.”—It is not, certainly, this monstruous conception which could be opposed, like a standard, to the false egalitarianism that aspires to the flattening of all through a common vulgarity. Fortunately, as long as there exists in the world the possibility of arranging two pieces of wood in the form of a cross—that is to say, always—humanity will continue believing that love is the foundation of every stable order and that hierarchical superiority in an order ought to be nothing else but a superior capacity for love!

                    A fountain of inexhaustible moral inspirations, a new science suggests to us, in order to clarify the laws of life, how the democratic principle can be reconciled, in the organization of human collectivities, with an aristarchy[2] of morality and culture.—On the one hand—as Henri Bérenger once noted in a sympathetic book[3]—the affirmations of science contribute to sanctioning and fortifying the spirit of democracy in society, revealing how great is the natural value of the collective force; how great the greatness of the work of the small; how immense the part of action reserved for the anonymous and obscure collaborator in any manifestation of universal development.  It raises, no less than revelation, the dignity of the humble, this new revelation, which attributes, in nature, to the work of the infinitely small, to the labor of the nummulite and bryozoan[4] in the obscure depth of the abyss, the construction of geological foundations; which causes all the ascendent impulse of organic forms from the vibration of the unformed and primitive cell; which manifests the powerful role that, in our psychical life, it is necessary to attribute to the more unapparent and vaguer phenomena, even to the fleeting perceptions of which we have no consciousness; and which, arriving at sociology and history, restores to heroism, often denounced by the crowds, the part that silence forbid it in the glory of the individual hero, and it makes clear the slow accumulation of the investigations which, across the centuries, in the shadow, in the workshop, or in the laboratory of forgotten workers, prepare the deeds of genius.

                    But, at the same time that it thus manifests the immortal efficacy of the collective force and dignifies the participation of the unknown collaborators in the universal work, science shows how, in the immense society of things and beings, hierarchical order is a necessary condition of all progress; how the relations of dependence and of subordination between the individual components of that society and between the elements of the organization of the individual are a principle of life; and, finally, how there is necessarily inherent in the universal law of imitation, if it is set in relation to the perfecting of human societies, the presence, in them, of living and influential models, which raise them up through the progressive generalization of their superiority.

                    In order to show, now, how both universal teachings of science can be translated into acts, being reconciled in the organization and in the spirit of society, it is enough to insist upon the conception of a noble, just democracy; of a democracy ruled by the notion and sentiment of true human superiorities; of a democracy in which supremacy of intelligence and virtue—the only limits for the meritorious equivalence of men—receives its authority and its prestige from liberty and descends upon the multitudes in a beneficial effusion of love.

                    At the same time that it reconciles those two great results of the observation of the natural order, it will realize, within a similar society—according to what Bérenger observes in the same book of which I spoke to you—the harmony of the two historical impulses that have communicated their essential characters to our civilization, the ruling principles of its life.—From the spirit of Christianity is born, effectively, the sentiment of equality, corrupted by a certain ascetic belittling of spiritual selection and culture.  From the inheritance of the classical civilizations is born the feeling of order, of hierarchy, and the religious respect for genius, corrupted by a certain aristocratic disdain for the humble and the weak.  The future will synthesize both suggestions from the past into an immortal formula.  Democracy, meanwhile, will have definitively triumphed.  And it, which, when it threatens with the ignobility of the flattening razor, justifies the irate protests and the bitter melancholy of those who believed that, through its triumph, every intellectual distinction, every dream of art, every delicacy of life was sacrificed, will have, even more than the old aristocracies, inviolable security for the cultivation of the flowers of the soul, would wilt and perish in the atmosphere of vulgarity and amid the impieties of mayhem!

 

Sources: José Enrique Rodó, Obras completas, ed. Emir Rodríguez Monegal (Madrid: Águilar, 1957).

Nicolás Gómez-Dávila, Escolios a un texto implícito (Girona: Atalanta, 2021).  

(Confusingly, the name Scholia to an Implicit Text is given both to Gómez-Dávila’s collected works and to his first two-volume book; this volume contains all of Gómez-Dávila’s aphoristic works, though all the passages I quoted are from that first two-volume work. )



[1] Alfred Jules Émile Fouillée (1838-1912), a French philosopher who strove to reconcile metaphysical idealism and positivistic science.

[2] Rodó is trying to distinguish aristocracy from aristarchy.  Both are related to rule by the best (aristos), but the second half of the names come from different Greek terms, kratos and arche.  Both can mean “rule,” but the former has a greater sense of ruling by force, by “might” or “power” (other translations of kratos), while the latter has more of a connotation of exercising authority or jurisdiction or leadership.

[3] Henri Bérenger (1867-1952) was a French senator for over thirty years (1912-1945), as well as, briefly (1926-1927), the French ambassador to the United States.  He was also a prolific author; Rodó is most likely referencing Bérenger’s 1895 book Intellectual Aristocracy.

[4] The nummulite is a single-celled protozoan famous for its tiny, coiled shells, which the ancient Egyptians used for currency (hence the name nummulite comes from the Latin nummulus, “little coin”).  A bryozoan is member of a phylum of aquatic, invertebrate animals.  Rodó is using both as examples of tiny, ancient, simple organisms whose cumulative acts caused large effects.

 

Translation ©2023 Brandon P. Otto.  Licensed via CC BY-NC.  Feel free to redistribute non-commercially, as long as credit is given to the translator.

 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

How to Discuss the Eastern Church: A Grammatical Primer

St. Gregory Palamas on the Graven Images

Franciscan Fasting